【英文读物】The Theory of the Leisure Class

更新时间:2023-05-29 14:32:11 阅读: 评论:0

公告【英文读物】The Theory of the Leisure Class
Chapter One ~~ Introductory
The institution of a leisure class is found in its best development at the higher stages of the barbarian culture; as, for instance, in feudal Europe or feudal Japan. In such communities the distinction between class is very rigorously obrved; and the feature of most striking economic significance in the class differences is the distinction maintained between the employments proper to the veral class. The upper class are by custom exempt or excluded from industrial occupations, and are rerved for certain employments to which a degree of honour attaches. Chief among the honourable employments in any feudal community is warfare; and priestly rvice is commonly cond to warfare. If the barbarian community is not notably warlike, the priestly office may take the precedence, with that of the warrior cond. But the rule holds with but slight exceptions that, whether warriors or priests, the upper class are exempt from industrial employments, and this exemption is the economic expression of their superior rank. Brahmin India affords a fair illustration of the industrial exemption of both the class. In the communities belonging to the higher barbarian culture there is a considerable differentiation of sub-class within what may be comprehensively called the leisure class; and there is a corresponding differentiation of employments between the sub-class. The leisure class as a who
le compris the noble and the priestly class, together with much of their retinue. The occupations of the class are correspondingly diversified; but they have the common economic characteristic of being non-industrial. The non-industrial upper-class occupations may be roughly comprid under government, warfare, religious obrvances, and sports.百思不得其解的意思
At an earlier, but not the earliest, stage of barbarism, the leisure class is found in a less differentiated form. Neither the class distinctions nor the distinctions between leisure-class occupations are so minute and intricate. The Polynesian islanders generally show this stage of the development in good form, with the exception that, owing to the abnce of large game, hunting does not hold the usual place of honour in their scheme of life. The Icelandic community in the time of the Sagas also affords a fair instance. In such a community there is a rigorous distinction between class and between the occupations peculiar to each class. Manual labour, industry, whatever has to do directly with the everyday work of getting a livelihood, is the exclusive occupation of the inferior class. This inferior class includes slaves and other dependents, and ordinarily also all the women. If there are veral grades of aristocracy, the women of high rank are commonly exempt from industrial employment, or at least from the more vulgar kinds of manual labour. The men of the upper class are not only exempt, but by prescriptive custom they are debarred, from all industrial occupations. The range of e
爱莫mployments open to them is rigidly defined. As on the higher plane already spoken of, the employments are government, warfare, religious obrvances, and sports. The four lines of activity govern the scheme of life of the upper class, and for the highest rank—the kings or chieftains—the are the only kinds of activity that custom or the common n of the community will allow. Indeed, where the scheme is well developed even sports are accounted doubtfully legitimate for the members of the highest rank. To the lower grades of the leisure class certain other employments are open,
but they are employments that are subsidiary to one or another of the typical leisure-class occupations. Such are, for instance, the manufacture and care of arms and accoutrements and of war canoes, the dressing and handling of hors, dogs, and hawks, the preparation of sacred apparatus, etc. The lower class are excluded from the condary honourable employments, except from such as are plainly of an industrial character and are only remotely related to the typical leisure-class occupations.三个馒头
If we go a step back of this exemplary barbarian culture, into the lower stages of barbarism, we no longer find the leisure class in fully developed form. But this lower barbarism shows the usages, motives, and circumstances out of which the institution of a leisure class has arin, and indicates th
e steps of its early growth. Nomadic hunting tribes in various parts of the world illustrate the more primitive phas of the differentiation. Any one of the North American hunting tribes may be taken as a convenient illustration. The tribes can scarcely be said to have a defined leisure class. There is a differentiation of function, and there is a distinction between class on the basis of this difference of function, but the exemption of the superior class from work has not gone far enough to make the designation "leisure class" altogether applicable. The tribes belonging on this economic level have carried the economic differentiation to the point at which a marked distinction is made between the occupations of men and women, and this distinction is of an invidious character. In nearly all the tribes the women are, by prescriptive custom, held to tho employments out of which the industrial occupations proper develop at the next advance. The men are exempt from the vulgar employments and are rerved for war, hunting, sports, and devout obrvances. A very nice discrimination is ordinarily shown in this matter.
This division of labour coincides with the distinction between the working and the leisure class as it appears in the higher barbarian culture. As the diversification and specialisation of employments proceed, the line of demarcation so drawn comes to divide the industrial from the non-industrial employments. The man's occupation as it stands at the earlier barbarian stage is not the original out
of which any appreciable portion of later industry has developed. In the later development it survives only in employments that are not clasd as industrial,—war, politics, sports, learning, and the priestly office. The only notable exceptions are a portion of the fishery industry and certain slight employments that are doubtfully to be clasd as industry; such as the manufacture of arms, toys, and sporting goods. Virtually the whole range of industrial employments is an outgrowth of what is clasd as woman's work in the primitive barbarian community.
培养孩子The work of the men in the lower barbarian culture is no less indispensable to the life of the group than the work done by the women. It may even be that the men's work contributes as much to the food supply and the other necessary consumption of the group. Indeed, so obvious is this "productive" character of the men's work that in the conventional economic writings the hunter's work is taken as the type of primitive industry. But such is not the barbarian's n of the matter. In his own eyes he is not a labourer, and he is not to be clasd with the women in this respect; nor is his effort to be clasd with the women's drudgery, as labour or industry, in such a n as to admit of its being confounded with the latter. There is in all barbarian communities a profound n of the disparity between man's and woman's work. His work may conduce to the maintenance of the group, but it is felt that it does so through an excellence and an efficacy of a kind that cannot without derogation be compared with the uneventful diligence
of the women.
更年期多大岁数开始At a farther step backward in the cultural scale—among savage groups—the differentiation of employments is still less elaborate and the invidious distinction between class and employments is less consistent and less rigorous. Unequivocal instances of a primitive savage culture are hard to find. Few of the groups or communities that are clasd as "savage" show no traces of regression from a more advanced cultural stage. But there are groups—some of them apparently not the result of retrogression—which show the traits of primitive savagery with some fidelity. Their culture differs from that of the barbarian communities in the abnce of a leisure class and the abnce, in great measure, of the animus or spiritual attitude on which the institution of a leisure class rests. The communities of primitive savages in which there is no hierarchy of economic class make up but a small and inconspicuous fraction of the human race. As good an instance of this pha of culture as may be had is afforded by the tribes of the Andamans, or by the Todas of the Nilgiri Hills. The scheme of life of the groups at the time of their earliest contact with Europeans ems to have been nearly typical, so far as regards the abnce of a leisure class. As a further instance might be cited the Ainu of Yezo, and, more doubtfully, also some Bushman and Eskimo groups. Some Pueblo communities are less confidently to be included in the same class. Most, if not all, of the communitie
s here cited may well be cas of degeneration from a higher barbarism, rather than bearers of a culture that has never rin above its prent level. If so, they are for the prent purpo to be taken with the allowance, but they may rve none the less as evidence to the same effect as if they were really "primitive" populations.
The communities that are without a defined leisure class remble one another also in certain other features of their social structure and manner of life. They are small groups and of a simple (archaic) structure; they are commonly peaceable and dentary; they are poor; and individual ownership is not a dominant feature of their economic system. At the same time it does not follow that the are the smallest of existing communities, or that their social structure is in all respects the least differentiated; nor does the class necessarily include all primitive communities which have no defined system of individual ownership. But it is to be noted that the class ems to include the most peaceable—perhaps all the characteristically peaceable—primitive groups of men. Indeed, the most notable trait common to members of such communities is a certain amiable inefficiency when confronted with force or fraud.
The evidence afforded by the usages and cultural traits of communities at a low stage of development indicates that the institution of a leisure class has emerged gradually during the transiti
on from primitive savagery to barbarism; or more precily, during the transition from a peaceable to a consistently warlike habit of life. The conditions apparently necessary to its emergence in a consistent form are: (1) the community must be of a predatory habit of life (war or the hunting of large game or both); that is to say, the men, who constitute the inchoate leisure class in the cas, must be habituated to the infliction of injury by force and stratagem; (2) subsistence must be obtainable on sufficiently easy terms to admit of the exemption of a considerable portion of the community from steady application to a routine of labour. The institution of leisure class is the outgrowth of an early discrimination between employments, according to which some employments are worthy and others unworthy. Under this ancient distinction the worthy employments are tho which may be clasd as exploit; unworthy are tho necessary everyday employments into which no appreciable element of exploit enters.
This distinction has but little obvious significance in a modern industrial community, and it has, therefore, received but slight attention at the hands of economic writers. When viewed in the light of that modern common n which has guided economic discussion, it ems formal and insubstantial. But it persists with great tenacity as a commonplace preconception even in modern life, as is shown, for instance, by our habitual aversion to menial employments. It is a distinction of a
personal kind—of superiority and inferiority. In the earlier stages of culture, when the personal force of the individual counted more immediately and obviously in shaping the cour of events, the element of exploit counted for more in the everyday scheme of life. Interest centred about this fact to a greater degree. Conquently a distinction proceeding on this ground emed more imperative and more definitive then than is the ca to-day. As a fact in the quence of development, therefore, the distinction is a substantial one and rests on sufficiently valid and cogent grounds.
The ground on which a discrimination between facts is habitually made changes as the interest from which the facts are habitually viewed changes. Tho features of the facts at hand are salient and substantial upon which the dominant interest of the time throws its light. Any given ground of distinction will em insubstantial to any one who habitually apprehends the facts in question from a different point of view and values them for a different purpo. The habit of distinguishing and classifying the various purpos and directions of activity prevails of necessity always and everywhere; for it is indispensable in reaching a working theory or scheme of life. The particular point of view, or the particular characteristic that is pitched upon as definitive in the classification of the facts of life depends upon the interest from which a discrimination of the facts is sought. The grounds of discrimination, and the norm of procedure in classifying the facts, therefore, progressively
change as the growth of culture proceeds; for the end for which the facts of life are apprehended changes, and the point of view conquently changes also. So that what are recognid as the salient and decisive features of a class of activities or of a social class at one stage of culture will not retain the same relative importance for the purpos of classification at any subquent stage.
But the change of standards and points of view is gradual only, and it ldom results in the subversion or entire suppression of a standpoint once accepted. A distinction is still habitually made between industrial and non-industrial occupations; and this modern distinction is a transmuted form of the barbarian distinction between exploit and drudgery. Such employments as warfare, politics, public worship, and public merrymaking, are felt, in the popular apprehension, to differ intrinsically from the labour that has to do with elaborating the material means of life. The preci line of demarcation is not the same as it was in the early barbarian scheme, but the broad distinction has not fallen into disu.
王者荣耀高清壁纸The tacit, common-n distinction to-day is, in effect, that any effort is to be accounted industrial only so far as its ultimate purpo is the utilisation of non-human things. The coercive utilisation of man by man is not felt to be an industrial function; but all effort directed to enhance human life by taking advantage of the non-human environment is clasd together as industrial activity. By the eco
nomists who have best retained and adapted the classical tradition, man's "power over nature" is currently postulated as the characteristic fact of industrial productivity. This industrial power over nature is taken to include man's power over the life of the beasts and over all the elemental forces. A line is in this way drawn between mankind and brute creation.
In other times and among men imbued with a different body of preconceptions this line is not
drawn precily as we draw it to-day. In the savage or the barbarian scheme of life it is drawn in a different place and in another way. In all communities under the barbarian culture there is an alert and pervading n of antithesis between two comprehensive groups of phenomena, in one of which barbarian man includes himlf, and in the other, his victual. There is a felt antithesis between economic and non-economic phenomena, but it is not conceived in the modern fashion; it lies not between man and brute creation, but between animate and inert things.
It may be an excess of caution at this day to explain that the barbarian notion which it is here intended to convey by the term "animate" is not the same as would be conveyed by the word "living". The term does not cover all living things, and it does cover a great many others. Such a striking natural phenomenon as a storm, a dia, a waterfall, are recognid as "animate"; while fruits and
herbs, and even inconspicuous animals, such as hou-flies, maggots, lemmings, sheep, are not ordinarily apprehended as "animate" except when taken collectively. As here ud the term does not necessarily imply an indwelling soul or spirit. The concept includes such things as in the apprehension of the animistic savage or barbarian are formidable by virtue of a real or imputed habit of initiating action. This category compris a large number and range of natural objects and phenomena. Such a distinction between the inert and the active is still prent in the habits of thought of unreflecting persons, and it still profoundly affects the prevalent theory of human life and of natural process; but it does not pervade our daily life to the extent or with the far-reaching practical conquences that are apparent at earlier stages of culture and belief. To the mind of the barbarian, the elaboration and utilisation of what is afforded by inert nature is activity on quite a different plane from his dealings with "animate" things and forces. The line of demarcation may be vague and shifting, but the broad distinction is sufficiently real and cogent to influence the barbarian scheme of life. To the class of things apprehended as animate, the barbarian fancy imputes an unfolding of activity directed to some end. It is this teleological unfolding of activity that constitutes any object or phenomenon an "animate" fact. Wherever the unsophisticated savage or barbarian meets with activity that is at all obtrusive, he construes it in the only terms that are ready to hand—the terms immediately given in his consciousness of his own actions. Activity is, therefore, assimilate罗马世家
d to human action, and active objects are in so far assimilated to the human agent. Phenomena of this character—especially tho who behaviour is notably formidable or baffling—have to be met in a different spirit and with proficiency of a different kind from what is required in dealing with inert things. To deal successfully with such phenomena is a work of exploit rather than of industry. It is an asrtion of prowess, not of diligence.
Under the guidance of this naive discrimination between the inert and the animate, the activities of the primitive social group tend to fall into two class, which would in modern phra be called exploit and industry. Industry is effort that goes to create a new thing, with a new purpo given it by the fashioning hand of its maker out of passive ("brute") material; while exploit, so far as it results in an outcome uful to the agent, is the conversion to his own ends of energies previously directed to some other end by an other agent. We still speak of "brute matter" with something of the barbarian's realisation of a profound significance in the term.
The distinction between exploit and drudgery coincides with a difference between the xes. The xes differ, not only in stature and muscular force, but perhaps even more decisively in temperament, and this must early have given ri to a corresponding division of labour. The

本文发布于:2023-05-29 14:32:11,感谢您对本站的认可!

本文链接:https://www.wtabcd.cn/fanwen/fan/89/947071.html

版权声明:本站内容均来自互联网,仅供演示用,请勿用于商业和其他非法用途。如果侵犯了您的权益请与我们联系,我们将在24小时内删除。

标签:读物   孩子   开始   王者   罗马
相关文章
留言与评论(共有 0 条评论)
   
验证码:
推荐文章
排行榜
Copyright ©2019-2022 Comsenz Inc.Powered by © 专利检索| 网站地图