8法律 外文翻译 外文文献 英文文献 法律中的违约责任

更新时间:2023-07-09 17:07:23 阅读: 评论:0

The breach of contract in French law: between safety of
expectations and efficiency
Pierre Garello∗
出去英语Faculte d’Economie Appliquée, Universite de Droit, d’Econimie et des Sciences d’ Aix-Marille,
3 Avenue Robert Schuman, Aix-en-Provence 13628, France
Accepted 20 August 2002
1.Introduction: which path will lead us to a better understanding of French contract law?
Contracts are marvellous tools to help us to live in a world of uncertainty. They allow us to project ourlves into an unknowable future, to invest. Lawyers who have inspired the French Civil law and contributed to its evolution, as well as most lawyers in the world, have clearly perceived the necessity to protect that institution. “The contract is, as far as the individual is concerned, the best forecasting instrument generating legal curity, and the favored path to freedom and responsibility that is necessary for the flourishing of human beings in a society.”1 Contracts are far from miraculous tools, h
owever. If they make life easier, they do not necessarily make life easy. As the future unfolds, one or both contracting parties may be tempted, or compelled, to break his or her promi. But, the mere fact that the contract is running into difficulties does not force the law to do something!2 It is only when one of the parties does not perform that the law (the court, the legislation), backed with coercive power, has to give an opinion, to decide the ca. In order to do so some principles, or theories, are required to reach a judgment as to what is the best thing to do.
铁艺旋转楼梯The prent study of the French contract law is bad on the premi that, from a law and economics point of view, there exists basically two possible ways to address this concern: the first approach requires that whenever a problem aris, an asssment be made of all costs and benefits incurred by the parties. In other words, one must attempt to evaluate in a sufficiently preci way the conquences of the court decision—or of the rule of law under consideration—for both parties as well as for third parties (including potential future contractors). The lawthen—and more precily here, contract law—should aim primarily at providing the right incentives to contracting parties, where by “right incentives” one means incentives to behave in such a way that the difference between social benefits and social costs be maximized. It will be argued below that French contract law sometimes follows this approach.
The cond possible attitude looks, apparently, pretty much like the first. The guiding principle is again that the law should provide to members of the society the right incentives. But one must immediately add that the judge—or the legislator, or the expert—is not in a position to evaluate and compare the social costs and benefits of alternative rules of law. He or she just does not know enough. One does not know, for instance, all the effects of a rule that would allow one party to breach a contract, without the connt of the other party. Indeed, even if the
victim of the breach is promid a fair compensation, allowing such a rule globally might have a negative effect on the very purpo of the institution, which is to reduce uncertainty. As a conquence, the law should adopt a goal less ambitious than the maximization of social well bei ng. That goal could be “to protect contracts,” or, in other terms, to create a t of incentives that lead individuals to feel confident that their legitimate expectations will be fulfilled.
As pointed out, tho two attitudes may appear the same, differing just in degree. The first one assumes more knowledge on the part of lawyers and legislators than the cond. However, when it comes to practical decision-making, differences turn out to be important, becau the more knowledgeable you think you are, the stronger will be the incentive to regulate the contract, and the lower will be the respect for tradition and customs on which daily expectations are bad.
The two approaches outlined above are well known to economists. The first one is the so-called “mainstream” (Paretian) approach and underlines most of the existing economic analysis of law.3 The cond one, stressing the problem of knowledge, is far less developed.4 We will call it the “safety-of-expectations approach,” or the Austrian approach to law an d economics, becau it can be found primarily in thework of the Austrian school of economic thought, and especially in Hayek’s studies.
“The rationale,” says Hayek, “of curing to each individual a known range within which he can decide on his actions is to enable him to make the fullest u of his knowledge, especially of his concrete and often unique knowledge of the particular circumstances of time and place. The law tells him what facts he may count on and thereby extends the range within which he can predict the conquences of his actions. At the same time it tells him what possible conquences of his actions he must take into account or what he will be held responsible for.”5
The reason why the two approaches are mentioned at the outt is that, when one studies French contract law, it is difficult to reconcile all of it with a single approach. True, the mainstream, neoclassical approach, bad on the assumption that rules be chon that maximize social wealth (or, at other times, that lead to a Pareto-efficient outcome), can help us to understand an important p
art of that body of law. But, as will be shown, certain French doctrines cannot be reconciled with neither a Paretian approach, nor a wealth maximizing approach. In some instances, the lawems to be more concerned with the safety of expectations.
In the next two ctions we will examine the main doctrines and rules of French contract law trying to identify tho that are compatible with both principles and tho that are compatible with only one. If none of tho ts are empty, it will mean that the French law of contract is not totally coherent; it cannot be brought under a unique unifying principle of explanation. The next natural questionwould then be whether French lawismoving towards one
principle and away from the other. However, this paper will not address this question.
The paper is organized in two parts. Indeed, for reasons briefly mentioned above, it is important to underline in a first part the many things the law does in order to avoid breach of contract: what can be done in order to save a contract when the parties are having difficulties performing, and what is forbidden? The cond part deals directly with the breach of contract. It will be shown that French law differs in some important respects from other contract laws. 2.Saving the contract6
We will study the various attempts to “save” the contract by looking first at the conditions for invalidit
y (Section 2.1), then at the various possibilities left to the judge to interpret the terms of the contract (Section 2.2) and end with the study of the cas where the judge is authorized to change the terms of the contract (Section 2.3).笋干焖五花肉
2.1. Invalid contracts
超轻粘土做花
One way to save the contract is to prove that there was no valid contract in the first place! Formation defens as defined in the French law are roughly identical to tho found in the contract laws of other countries. The main defens are: incompetency (incapacité), mistakes (erreur), fraud (dol), duress (violence), abnce of cau (reminding us of the doctrine of consideration in the bargaining theory), failure to disclo information, lésion (a defen clo to unconscionability),7 or, may be more specific to French law, a conflict between the private agreement and ordre public, i.e. public policy, or “law and order” (e art. 6 and 1134 of the French Civil Code, henceforth C.civ.). In all the instances, an action may be taken for annulment of the contract, the judge being the only one entitled to invalidate a contract.
But, what exactly is meant by invalidity in the French law? What are the conquences? The French law distinguishes between absolute invalidity (nullitéabsolue) and relative invalidity (nullité relative).
The first category includes all the contracts that are against what is called ordre public de direction, that is to say, contracts that violate a public policy judged to be beneficial to the society as a whole and not only to tho individuals involved in that particular contract. For such contracts nothing can be done and complete nullity cannot be avoided. The cond category is made of contracts that violate the ordre public de protection, that is, contracts in which one party does not respect a public policy designed to protect weaker parties. In tho circumstances, the victim who the law is trying to protect may choo to let the contract stand after modifications to the contract.8
In both cas, however, the result is as if the contract had never existed, and retroactivity with restitution is the general principle: one is suppod to go back to the situation that prevailed before the contract was created: the status quo ante. Parties are relieved of their obligations, and damages can no longer be awarded, but it is still possible to bring a tort law action.9车险买哪些
From an economic point of view, most of the formation defens mentioned have already
勤俭节约
been analyzed in various places, the bottom line being: any contract that is not voluntary must be considered as invalid. One can e however that, from a strictly Paretian point of view, it is not clear that all involuntary contracts—e.g. contracts relying on a mistake—will always be dominated by the s
ituation prevailing before the contract. If one choos the Hayekian, safety-of-expectations point of view, such a dilemma is less likely to occur to the extent that people expect transactions to be voluntary. Conquently, any involuntary transaction violates some “legitimate expectations.”
Before leaving the topic of nullity, two interesting facts derve attention. First, it must be pointed out that exceptions exist to the general principle of retroactivity with restitution. In particular, if the contract is null due to the deliberate action of one of the parties (e.g. In the ca of fraud), the principle is softened; the victim sometimes will not have to return the object, or the payment. The action for annulment can even be rejected by the judge if this favors the victim. Finally, becau few cas of fraud are brought to court, the legislator has stepped in to regulate the contractual process. This is the ca, for instance, with the law of August 1, 1905 on fraud (now part of consumer law, Code de la Consommation, article L. 213–1), or the law of December 27, 1973 on advertising (today C. Consommation a. L.124–1).10 Legislation sometimes eks to protect potential victims of fraudulent behaviour. This type of intervention can be easily justified in the Paretian or wealth-maximization frameworks becau it reduces some transaction costs. It is better that the law nds clear signals to potential wrongdoers than to correct wrongdoings once they have occurred. From an Hayekian perspective, the benefits of such intervention are less evident becau you have to take int
o account the fact that the potential victims may, as a result, be less careful, and behave in a less responsible way. In any ca, one should keep in mind that courts consider invalidity to be something exceptional. “To restrict as much as possible the number of nullity cas ems to fit with the contemporary need to bring more curity to business.”11.
2.2. Interpreting the contract
To save the contract, the judge may have to interpret its terms or to modify them. When reading legal scholars on the topics, one comes rapidly to the conclusion that there is no unanimity in France about what is the proper role for the judge when performance is problematic. As explains Ghestin: “Hence, always referring to justice, it is possible to forbid to the judge any intervention, or at the opposite, and as is done today, to justify his/her corrective interference, so that he/she can guarantee that there is at least a relative balance between the promis that are being exchanged.”12 This analysis can also be found in Delebecque, Pansier: The role of the judge in appreciating the terms of the contract is a matter of great controversy.南京大学研究生分数线
On one hand, you may wish to deprive the judge of any power arguing that he is not a party to the contract; conquently, the judge should never intervene, nor modify such and such
elements of the contract. On the other hand, one can admit the intervention of the judge in contractual matters in order to introduce a light wind of fairness in the contract. The law is rather bad on the first approach.Indeed, as we have noticed already, the legislator allows himlf or herlf the right to perfect and regulate some contracts, and the judge, stimulated and reassured by such intervention, has decided that he also as a right to step in.13 Keeping in mind this controversy, let us e what the French written law says.
A major principle of French law is juridical connsualism (connsualisme juridique). Deeply rooted in French tradition—it goes back to the 18th century and became prominent in the 15th century14—this principle is cloly related to a more recent one: the autonomy of the will.15 In contractual matters this means that the contract should be interpreted, not literally, but according to good faith. This is also called the subjective method of interpretation and is grounded in art. 1156 to 1164 C.civ.: “As far as conventions are concerned, one must look for the common intention of the contracting parties rather than look for the literal meaning of the terms” (art. 1156 C.civ.). Now, if to interpret is to try to rediscover what the parties really wanted, does this method make n from an economic point of view, or should it be changed for the objective method?
On the bright side, whether you are Paretian or Austrian, you can argue that this method of interpret
ation reduces transaction costs since the parties may leave the contract incomplete: if necessary, the judge—or more generally, the law through default rules—will interpret the contract as they would have written it, if it was not for the cost of writing done a complete contract. Not only that, but the very possibility to leave gaps in the contract may be desirable to allow the parties to signal a high degree of confidence that promis will be performed; in other words, gaps may be uful strategic tools.
经济重心的南移On the dark side, it may be pointed out that the objective method, chon in other countries such as Germany, forces the parties to be more explicit on what they expect and this, in turn, may reduce future transaction costs. Also it should be recalled that it is not always easy to interpret the will of the parties, and it is good for that reason to give them strong incentives to fill up as many gaps as possible.
Anyway, the French law will not let the judge interpret the terms of the contract, or fill gaps as it pleas her. The judge will have to follow certain rules. Here are some of them.16 First maxim: better to interpret the contract in such a way that it will survive (art. 1157 C.civ.). Again one can read here an a priori in favour of voluntary exchanges which, as was pointed out earlier, is economically sound. It is also the desire to avoid that efforts invested in the contractual relationship be wasted.
Second maxim (only for unilateral contracts such as loan contracts): the judge should interpret the contract in the way which is most favorable to the debtor (art. 1162 C.civ.). One can perceive two economic reasons to this rule. Firstly, it increas the probability of

本文发布于:2023-07-09 17:07:23,感谢您对本站的认可!

本文链接:https://www.wtabcd.cn/fanwen/fan/89/1074662.html

版权声明:本站内容均来自互联网,仅供演示用,请勿用于商业和其他非法用途。如果侵犯了您的权益请与我们联系,我们将在24小时内删除。

标签:铁艺   笋干   超轻   研究生
相关文章
留言与评论(共有 0 条评论)
   
验证码:
推荐文章
排行榜
Copyright ©2019-2022 Comsenz Inc.Powered by © 专利检索| 网站地图