[经济学]个人主义的当代观点-从亚当斯密到哈耶克

更新时间:2023-05-29 03:39:21 阅读: 评论:0

I NDIVIDUALISM IN M ODERN T HOUGHT: F ROM A DAM
S MITH TO H AYEK. B Y L ORENZO I NFANTINO. L ONDON AND N EW Y ORK: R OUTLEDGE, 1998
P rofessor Infantino has applied his considerable skills to the task of freeing英语四级准考证打印
the social sciences from the deforming constraints of methodological collectivism. Relying on the methodological individualism pioneered and developed by Bernard de Mandeville, Adam Smith, Herbert Spencer, Carl Menger, Ludwig von Mis, Friedrich Hayek and Karl Popper, Infantino renders a parsimoni-ous statement of the theory of unintentional order. As a sociologist, he directs his colleagues to the similar themes that inform the writings of Georg Simmel and Max Weber in the larger context of his arching examinations of the constructivistic modes of thought so thoroughly ingrained in the major works of Émile Durkheim and Talcott Parsons.
mild
Tho who followed in the wake of Mandeville and Smith have made it possible to locate each of the major elements of unintentional order in the minal writings. Therein, the human species is treated as social in its origins and constrained by what Infantino calls a “double-entry of account.” Ego acting in view of his or her own interests depends upon means supplied by Others. To cure the means, Ego
itemnomust supply material and rvices that are means to Others, ud in furthering their own interests, which need not be approved by nor even known to Ego. Ego’s own plan becomes a constituent part of a composition of individual actions that no one could have planned nor even imagined, ex ante.
Over his first three chapters, Infantino provides ample demonstration that the social glue that has been of such great concern to sociologists is clearly recogniz-able in the concessions individuals are bound to offer one another in the cour of accumulating the means of their own satisfactions. The are the norms most relevant to the sociological enterpri. Arising directly out of interaction, they measure “the relationships which actually exist in society” (p. 17). The alternatives so prominently displayed in the mainstream of sociological theory and rearch are norms impod by authority. At best, they measure relationships as imagined by an elite, which also eks to bring them about.
In the ca of economic exchange, norms appear in the form of prices. But if prices are merely the costs that individuals must accept to further their own action plans, they can be generalized to encompass all the accommodations and conces-sions individuals extend to others in social exchange—which itlf is inclusive of all varieties of purely voluntary social interaction. Following a logical and painstaking argument, Infantino embellishes his thesis with the simple obrvation that “It is not by chance that Smith’s ‘invisible hand’ was reprented by a network of prices, and the ‘imparti
al spectator’ was constituted by a network of norms” (p. 163).
The Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics vol. 2, no. 1 (1999): 87–92
冰河世纪3恐龙的黎明87
88THE QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF AUSTRIAN ECONOMICS VOL. 2, NO. 1 (SPRING1999) In his endeavor to communicate effectively with sociological colleagues, Infantino has had to overcome a number of potential obstacles, some of which are merely historical and others more directly theoretical. On the historical side, he corrects the impression that Adam Smith found any substantive grounds for disagreement with Mandeville. Despite Smith’s asrtion that Mandeville’s no-tions were “in almost every respect erroneous,” Infantino has juxtapod a suffi-ciency of passages from the works of both authors to establish their theoretical consistency. Turning more directly toward the theoretical, he dissolves the putative inconsistency between Smith’s writings in Moral Sentiments and Wealth of Nations by demonstrating that “impartial spectator” and “invisible hand” coexist easily in the earlier work. Once the preten of logical moral foundations has been rejected, as it was not only by Mandeville and Smith, but also by Hume, any fundamental distinction between the two ideas must vanish.汽车机油常识
tachi
Sociologists should take a lively interest in this discussion, wherein they will appreciate the contours of C.H. Cooley’s “looking glass lf,” G.H. Mead’s “gener-alized other” and a neat sorting out of the social-scientific meaning that can properly be associated with the idea of “sympathy.” Relying on Adam Smith (1976, pp. 158–59), Infantino suggests that sympathy merely allows us to e “ourlves as others e us or as they would e us if they knew everything about us” (p. 25). Nothing in the concept links sympathy to a sharing of values or goals. As he says,“sympathy is not a ntiment,” and “putting onelf in the Other’s place does not mean sharing his ‘ntiments’; it is simply equivalent to adopting his obrvation post” (pp. 29–30). Tho who introduction to the history of social thought may have been slighted or forgotten should be impresd by the social psychological sophistication of the eighteenth-century writers. They insisted on the primacy of learning over “nature” and the utter importance of what we now call “primary socialization.” However strongly contemporary sociologists and social psycholo-gists may agree on the points, they appear hesitant to allow historical applica-tions, which would eliminate the idea that human beings have depended at some critical point on the bequest of a societal template from some mysterious source or other.
On the theoretical side most directly, Infantino has been obliged to grapple with the sociological conc
cinaept of unequal exchange. His treatment of this matter is excellent, but he may have underestimated the importance of the concept to many sociologists and the tenacity with which they embrace it. The mainstream of the sociological literature on inequality is grounded in one way or another on the possibility of unequal exchange. Infantino traces the basic idea to the mercantilists who held exchange to be a zero-sum proposition (p. 39). The theory of uninten-tional order, beginning with the ideas of specialization and the division of labor, depends fundamentally on an exchange process that is positive sum. It is equally clear that methodological collectivism depends just as heavily on mercantilist teachings, reworked as may be, into a neoclassical form that can be described as empirical at final equilibrium (e.g., Coleman 1990) or into a Durkheimian form wherein the values of an elite can stand proxy for the dictates of a collective conscience (e.g., Blau 1964). This is not the place to discuss the sociological affinity for the zero-sum game. Suffice it to say that Infantino has rested his ca on absolutely solid ground. Exchange is an analytic concept that, by definition, excludes every element of force and fraud. Whether or not an absolutely pure
BOOK REVIEWS89 exchange has ever been transacted between two human beings is clearly not an empirical question insofar as we are dealing with axioms; but the conceptual distinction is perfectly clear. In defen of the sociologists, it can be said that once the actor and action have been
banished, Weber’s distinction between class (market) and party (power) becomes meaningless and with it the distinction between exchange and coercion.
The ambivalence of sociologists to the prence of actors emerges as an important theme in the critical chapters that follow. The incorporation of choice leaves ample space for ignorance, error, force, and fraud; but the contrary does not hold. If choice is eliminated, nothing remains but stimulus and respon. Notwith-standing the diminishing residuals of ignorance and error, it will no longer matter whether one says that respons have been triggered, elicited, induced, or co-erced.
Durkheim is treated over two chapters that illustrate almost paradoxically how a thoroughgoing constructivistic cast of mind can be transformed—with only nominal changes—into a consistent statement of the cybernetics of unintentional order. Durkheim’s most glaring deficit was his ignorance of the economics of his day. His polemics directed at economists, members of the “Orthodox School,”etc., are remarkable in their neglect of formal citation. Infantino quotes Bergson, who wrote that with Durkheim “one never encountered a fact” (quoted in Lukes 1972, p. 52). Infantino reveals Durkheim’s strawman as none other than John Stuart Mill. This choice is remarkable in view of the avalanche of new ideas which animated the social sciences in the wake of a still recent marginalist revolution.
Durkheim’s caricature of economists as positing “originally isolated and inde-pendent individuals, who conquently enter into relationship only to co-operate”(Durkheim 1964, p. 279) was irresponsibly fal in 1893, but was carried forward nonetheless by Parsons and continues to this day to inform the sociological view of its own raison d’etre. The Durkheimian solution to a problem of order, which could not have been approached by the economists he imagined, was to cast the State as the supreme “organ of moral discipline” (Durkheim 1958, p. 72), making it an independent variable in the Hegelian manner (p. 63).
Durkheim never ventured into the arena of social origins. He was content merely to stress the impossibility that any such creature as homo economicus could have emerged to take on the task of societal architect. From this vantage point, he felt justified in arguing that society could only be a phenomenon sui generis. Infantino’s explication of this troublesome concept focus on Durk-heim’s decision to disallow by consideration the results of interaction by its principal parties in favor of a real third person upon whom the results became crystallized. This third person becomes the common nsorium that subordi-nates individuals to the common goals, which, in Durkheim’s view, were necessary to society’s existence (p. 75). In defen of the Open Society, here and in subquent chapters, Infantino is only obliged to defend the proposition that human beings benefit (or suffer) fro
m their own experiences. If this is true then the “privileged point of view on the world” must be that of a recognizable elite and not a reality sui generis. He places Durkheim’s method in the larger context of collectivist thought, “with its conceit of defining the social Absolute” which will always be limited to “placing some individuals in an unjustified position of privilege” (p. 76).
90THE QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF AUSTRIAN ECONOMICS VOL. 2, NO. 1 (SPRING1999) Infantino us chapter 5 to draw out the detailed struggle between Durkheim’s profound disdain for the market and his most genuine sociological insights. By carefully noting Durkheim’s frequent laps into methodological individualism, he is able to reconcile Durkheim both with Herbert Spencer and Georg Simmel. “The price to be paid” for this reconciliation “is the elimination of ‘social realism,’”whereas “The advantages lie in the possibility of reaching a clear sociological method, and of throwing full light on the complex phenomenon that is uninten-tional order” (p. 98).
Chapter 6 documents the methodological individualism that had developed in sociology a generation before Talcott Parsons embarked upon a career that established his preeminence over a generation of sociological theoreticians. Infantino compares key writings of Carl Menger with tho of Simmel and then examines the work of Max Weber aided by the critical eye of Ludwig von Mis. Following Menger, Simmel rejected the central thesis of historical realism—that “historical science is simply a
mirror image of the event ‘as it really hap-pened’”—in favor of an a priori argument to which historians resort, if only implicitly, to arrange the “facts” into patterns of relief and background (Simmel 1977, pp. vii–viii and 76–77). With Menger he asrted the evolutionary origins of money as a tool capable of being put to a variety of unforeeable us. Simmel’s contention that purely monetary obligations are tho most congruent with personal freedom derives from the paration that money affords between rvices rendered and the goals that are privately pursued by actors. This opens our view to “a society that renounces a ‘unitary’ system of ends” (p. 114).
Max Weber treated sociology as universal history rather than as a social science “that aims at universally valid propositions” (Mis 1976, p. 106). Professor Infantino is thus obliged to reduce Weber’s four-fold typology to the fundamental dichotomy of “value-rational” and “instrumentally rational” ac-tions, on the way to prenting the ideas and insights that most evidently place him in the tradition of methodological individualism (p. 129).如何在网上学习英语
trample6Weber rejected “psychologism,” arguing that sociology bears no clor rela-tion to psychology than to any other science. He was among the first to derive declining marginal utility from the multiplicity of means and ends in the face of scarcity, independently of any physiological or psychological tendencies to satia-tion. Along with Boris Brutzkus and Mis, he grasped the importance of market
prices for calculations that could approach any reasonable standard of economic efficiency. Most importantly, Weber insisted on the ultimacy of the individual in social action. For some cognitive purpos, entities such as associations, corpo-rations, and states could “be treated as the subjects of rights and duties or as the performers of legally significant actions.” But Weber immediately specified that “the subjective interpretation of action in sociological work” necessitated treatment of the collectivities “as solely the resultants and modes of organiza-tion of the particular acts of individual persons” (Weber 1978, p. 107). To acknowledge the particular acts of individual persons is to avoid the constructivist reification, which discovers them as mere emanations of the supraindividual.
Infantino’s final substantive chapter is devoted to the early Parsons, introduced as an individual who most basic impuls directed him to illuminate what he considered the necessarily moral foundations of human society by means of a
BOOK REVIEWS91 sociology in which the explanation of social action could be found in its justifica-tion (pp. 158–59). Impresd perhaps by the startling success of Mendeleev and others in the physical sciences, Parsons conceived a continuum for the sciences that began on the left, let us say, with the sciences of ultimate means such as physics and chemistry which deal with matter itlf. Lyin
g to the right of the sciences were tho like engineering and economics which treat the relation between means and ends. On this basis Parsons felt competent to predict the science of “ultimate ends,” i.e., sociology—awaiting discovery at the right extrem-ity of the continuum. He failed to note that metaphysics is located to the left of physics, nor did he consider that his own creation might turn out to be of similar stuff.
Infantino documents Parsons’s misreading of Spencer, his neglect of Simmel, and his embrace of Weber’s failure, t out in the previous chapter, to grasp that individuals who pursue duty, honor, and beauty to the neglect of material gain tho value the former more highly. Parsons was thus dispod to treat the voluntarism in his action theory as a species of submission to a transcendent normative order already outlined by Durkheim. Infantino notes Parsons’s criticism that Durkheim’s “individ-ual” is a mere theoretical abstraction. As Parsons (1949, p. 355) said, this individual “is the fictional human being who has never entered into any social relationship.”If the fictional human being is eliminated, however, we must protest with Professor Infantino that “society cannot be a sui generis reality, greater than the sum of its parts”(p. 152). Parsons was required at this juncture to choo between the concrete and the fictional actor—but he did not. Infantino finds the roots of this obstinate inconsis-tency in Parsons’s moralism reinforced by a refusal to consider the unintended conquences of action.
The question of importance, both to citizens and theoreticians, is whether social order emerges from a network of conditions. If it does, there is no need for an impod order of ultimate ends. On the other hand, of cour, if the network of conditions is powerless, individuals are powerless to act freely on their own behalf and must be duly constrained. What Durkheim, Parsons, or any of us may perceive as a consistent collection of ends is, in reality, a collection of means embedded in the conditions we impo upon each other for their reciprocal appropriation. Action can thus be explained, as Infantino says, “by means of the personal objective of the actor, and it can be justified through socially accepted ‘reasons’, in which the ‘conditions’ impod on Ego by the Other are reflected” in a “double-en-try of account” (p. 159).混蛋英语
In concluding, Infantino summarizes the elements of any theory of intentional order as psychologism, the rational construction of preferences, and the idea that the results of social action can be conceived as a process of maximization (p. 169). Against the prescriptions he offers a view that, despite its venerable age, remains revolutionary. We learn to be lves after ttling within ourlves the models, norms, and beliefs we have absorbed from the sociohistorical context into which we are born.
Tho familiar with Professor Infantino’s sources will be delighted by the efficient ea of his argume
nts. Others, who read with a critical eye, will appreciate his well-documented invitations to the minal works which inform his views. Before adopting the term “praxeology” to designate the most fundamental of the sciences of human action, Ludwig von Mis had referred to this discipline as

本文发布于:2023-05-29 03:39:21,感谢您对本站的认可!

本文链接:https://www.wtabcd.cn/fanwen/fan/78/803926.html

版权声明:本站内容均来自互联网,仅供演示用,请勿用于商业和其他非法用途。如果侵犯了您的权益请与我们联系,我们将在24小时内删除。

下一篇:c2
标签:汽车   打印   冰河   机油   准考证
相关文章
留言与评论(共有 0 条评论)
   
验证码:
推荐文章
排行榜
Copyright ©2019-2022 Comsenz Inc.Powered by © 专利检索| 网站地图