The coming into being of the notion of "author" constitutes the privileged moment of individualization in the history of ideas, knowledge, literature, philosophy, and the sciences. Even today, when we reconstruct the history of a concept, literary genre, or school of philosophy, such categories em relatively weak, condary, and superimpod scansions in comparison with the solid and fundamental unit of the author and the work. I shall not offer here a sociohistorical analysis of the author's persona. Certainly, it would be worth examining how the author became individualized in a culture like ours, what status he has been given, at what moment studies of authenticity and attribution began, in what kind of system of valorization the author was involved, at what point we began to recount the lives of authors rather than of heroes, and how this fundamental category of "the-man-and-his-work criticism" began. For the moment, however, I want to deal solely with the relationship between text and author and with the manner in which the text points to this figure that, at least in appearance; is outside it and antecedes it. Beckett nicely formulates the theme with which I would like to begin: "What does it matter who is speaking;' someone said; 'what does it matter who is speaking.'" In this indifference appears one of the fundamental ethical principles of contemporary writing [écriture]. I say "ethical" becau this indifference is really not a trait characterizing the manner in which one speaks and writes but, rather, a kind of immanent rule, taken up over and over again, never fully applied, not designating writing as something completed, but dominating it as a practice. Since it is too familiar to require a lengthy analysis, this immanent rule can be adequately illustrated here by tracing two of its major themes. First of all, we can say that today's writing has freed itlf from the theme of expression. Referring only to itlf; but without being restricted to the confines of its interiority, writing is identified with its own unfolded exteriority. This means that it is an interplay of signs arranged less according to its signified content than according to the very nature of the signifier. Writing unfolds like a game [jeu] that invariably goes beyond its own rules and transgress its limits. In writing, the point is not to manifest or exalt the act of writing, nor is it to pin a subject within language; it is, rather, a question of creating a space into which the writing subject constantly disappears. The cond theme, writing's relationship with death, is even more familiar. This link subverts an old tradition exemplified by the Greek epic, which was intended to perpetuate the immortality of the hero: if he was willing to die young, it was so that his life, concrated and magnified by death, might pass into immortality; the narrative then redeemed this accepted death. In another way, the motivation, as well as the theme and the pretext of Arabian narratives – such as The Thousand and One Nights – was also the eluding of death: one spoke, telling stories into the early morning, in order to forestall death, to postpone the day of reckoning that would silence the narrator. Scheherazade's narrative is an effort, renewed each night, to keep death outside the circle of life. 100教育一对一价格Our culture has metamorphod this idea of narrative, or writing, as something designed to ward off death. Writing has become linked to sacrifice, even to the sacrifice of life: it is now a voluntary effacement that does not need to be reprented in books, since it is brought about in the writer's very existence. The work, which once had the duty of providing immortality, now posss the right to kill, to be its author's murderer, as in the cas of Flaubert, Proust, and Kafka. That is not all, however: this relationship between writing and death is also manifested in the effacement of the writing subject's individual characteristics. Using all the contrivances that he ts up between himlf and what he writes, the writing subject cancels out the signs of his particular individuality. As a result, the mark of the writer is reduced to nothing more than the singularity of his abnce; he must assume the role of the dead man in the game of writing. None of this is recent; criticism and philosophy took note of the disappearance – or death - of the author some time ago. But the conquences of their discovery of it have not been sufficiently examined, nor has its import been accurately measured. A certain number of notions that are intended to replace the privileged position of the author actually em to prerve that privilege and suppress the real meaning of his disappearance. I shall examine two of the notions, both of great importance today. The first is the idea of the work [oeuvre]. It is a very familiar thesis that the task of criticism is not to bring out the work's relationships with the author, nor to reconstruct through the text a thought or experience, but rather to analyze the work through its structure, its architecture, its intrinsic form, and the play of its internal relationships. At this point, however, a problem aris: What is a work? What is this curious unity which we designate as a work? Of what elements is it compod? Is it not what an author has written? Difficulties appear immediately. If an individual were not an author, could we say that what he wrote, said, left behind in his papers, or what has been collected of his remarks, could be called a "work"? When Sade was not considered an author, what was the status of his papers? Simply rolls of paper onto which he cealessly uncoiled his fantasies during his imprisonment. Even when an individual has been accepted as an author, we must still ask whether everything that he wrote, said, or left behind is part of his work. The problem is both theoretical and technical. When undertaking the publication of Nietzsche's works, for example, where should one stop? Surely everything must be published, but what is "everything"? Everything that Nietzsche himlf published, certainly. And what about the rough drafts for his works? Obviously. The plans for his aphorisms? Yes. The deleted passages and the notes at the bottom of the page? Yes. What if, within a workbook filled with aphorisms, one finds a reference, the notation of a meeting or of an address, or a laundry list: is it a work, or not? Why not? And so on, ad infinitum. How can one define a work amid the millions of traces left by someone after his death? A theory of the work does not exist, and the empirical task of tho who naively undertake the editing of works often suffers in the abnce of such a theory. bottom什么意思We could go even further. Does The Thousand and One Nights constitute a work? What about Clement of Alexandria's Miscellaniesinteract or Diogenes Laërtes' Lives? A multitude of questions aris with regard to this notion of the work. Conquently, it is not enough to declare that we should do without the writer (the author) and study the work itlf. The word work and the unity that it designates are probably as problematic as the status of the author's individuality. Another notion which has hindered us from taking full measure of the author's disappearance, blurring and concealing the moment of this effacement and subtly prerving the author's existence, is the notion of writing [écriture]. When rigorously applied, this notion should allow us not only to circumvent references to the author, but also to situate his recent abnce. The notion of writing, as currently employed, is concerned with neither the act of writing nor the indication – be it symptom or sign – of a meaning that someone might have wanted to express. We try, with great effort, to imagine the general condition of each text, the condition of both the space in which it is disperd and the time in which it unfolds. In current usage, however, the notion of writing ems to transpo the empirical characteristics of the author into a transcendental anonymity. We are content to efface the more visible marks of the author's empiricity by playing off, one against the other, two ways of characterizing writing, namely, the critical and the religious approaches. Giving writing a primal status ems to be a way of retranslating, in transcendental terms, both the theological affirmation of its sacred character and the critical affirmation of its creative character. To admit that writing is, becau of the very history that it made possible, subject to the test of oblivion and repression, ems to reprent, in transcendental terms, the religious principle of the hidden meaning (which requires interpretation) and the critical principle of implicit signification, silent determinations, and obscured contents (which give ri to commentary). To imagine writing as abnce ems to be a simple repetition, in transcendental terms, of both the religious principle of inalterable and yet never fulfilled tradition, and the aesthetic principle of the work's survival, its perpetuation beyond the author's death, and its enigmatic excess in relation to him. This usage of the notion of writing runs the risk of maintaining the author's privileges under the protection of the a priori: it keeps alive, in the gray light of neutralization, the interplay of tho reprentations that formed a particular image of the author. The author's disappearance, which, since Mallarmé, has been a constantly recurring event, is subject to a ries of transcendental barriers. There ems to be an important dividing line between tho who believe that they can still locate today's discontinuities [ruptures] in the historico-transcendental tradition of the nineteenth century and tho who try to free themlves once and for all from that tradition.acapela show girl§ It is not enough, however, to repeat the empty affirmation that the author has disappeared. For the same reason, it is not enough to keep repeating that God and man have died a common death. Instead, we must locate the space left empty by the author's disappearance, follow the distribution of gaps and breaches, and watch for the openings this disappearance uncovers. First, we need to clarify briefly the problems arising from the u of the author's name. What is an author's name? How does it function? Far from offering a solution, I shall only indicate some of the difficulties that it prents. The author's name is a proper name, and therefore it rais the problems common to all proper names. (Here I refer to Searle's analys, among others.') Obviously, one cannot turn a proper name into a pure and simple reference. It has other than indicative functions: more than an indication, a gesture, a finger pointed at someone, it is the equivalent of a description. When one says "Aristotle," one employs a word that is the equivalent of one, or a ries, of definite descriptions, such as "the author of the Analytics," "the founder of ontology," and so forth. One cannot stop there, however, becau a proper name does not have just one signification. When we discover that Arthur Rimbaud did not write La Chas spirituelle, we cannot pretend that the meaning of this proper name, or that of the author, has been altered. The proper name and the author's name are situated between the two poles of description and designation: they must have a certain link with what they name, but one that is neither entirely in the mode of designation nor in that of description; it must be a specific link. However - and it is here that the particular difficulties of the author's name ari - the links between the proper name and the individual named and between the author's name and what it names are not isomorphic and do not function in the same way. There are veral differences. If for example, Pierre Dupont does not have blue eyes, or was not born in Paris, or is not a doctor, the name Pierre Dupont will still always refer to the same person, such things do not modify the link of designation. The problems raid by the author's name are much more complex, however. If I discover that Shakespeare was not born in the hou we visit today, this is a modification that, obviously, will not alter the functioning of the author's name. But if we proved that Shakespeare did not write tho sonnets which pass for his, that would constitute a significant change and affect the manner in which the author's name functions. If we proved that Shakespeare wrote Bacon's Organon by showing that the same author wrote both the works of Bacon and tho of Shakespeare, that would be a third type of change that would entirely modify the functioning of the author's name. The author's name is not, therefore, just a proper name like the rest. 任务型教学法Many other facts point out the paradoxical singularity of the author's name. To say that Pierre Dupont does not exist is not at all the same as saying that Homer or Hermes Trismegistus did not exist. In the first ca, it means that no one has the name Pierre Dupont; in the cond, it means that veral people were mixed together under one name, or that the true author had none of the traits traditionally ascribed to the personae of Homer or Hermes. To say that X's real name is actually Jacques Durand instead of Pierre Dupont is not the same as saying that Stendhal's name was Henri Beyle. One could also question the meaning and functioning of propositions like "Bourbaki is so-and-so, so-and-so, and so-forth," and "Victor Eremite, Climacus, Anticlimacus, Prater Taciturnus, Constantine Constantius, all of the are Kierkegaard." The differences may result from the fact that an author's name is not simply an element in a discour (capable of being either subject or object, of being replaced by a pronoun, and the like); it performs a certain role with regard to narrative discour, assuring a classificatory function. Such a name permits one to group together a certain number of texts, define them, differentiate them from and contrast them to others. In addition, it establishes a relationship among the texts. Hermes Trismegistus did not exist, nor did Hippocrates - in the n that Balzac existed - but the fact that veral texts have been placed under the same name indicates that there has been established among them a relationship of homogeneity, filiation, authentication of some texts by the u of others, reciprocal explication, or concomitant utilization. The author's name rves to characterize a certain mode of being of discour: the fact that the discour has an author's name, that one can say "this was written by so-and-so" or "so-and-so is its author," shows that this discour is not ordinary everyday speech that merely comes and goes, not something that is immediately consumable. On the contrary, it is a speech that must be received in a certain mode and that, in a given culture, must receive a certain status. It would em that the author's name, unlike other proper names, does not pass from the interior of a discour to the real and exterior individual who produced it; instead, the name ems always to be prent, marking off the edges of the text, revealing, or at least characterizing, its mode of being. The author's name manifests the appearance of a certain discursive t and indicates the status of this discour within a society and a culture. It has no legal status, nor is it located in the fiction of the work; rather, it is located in the break that founds a certain discursive construct and its very particular mode of being. As a result, we could say that in a civilization like our own there area certain number of discours endowed with the "author function" while others are deprived of it. A private letter may well have a signer – it does not have an author; a contract may well have a guarantor – it does not have an author. An anonymous text posted on a wall probably has an editor – but not an author. The author function is therefore characteristic of the mode of existence, circulation, and functioning of certain discours within a society. § Let us analyze this "author function" as we have just described it. In our culture, how does one characterize a discour containing the author function? In what way is this discour different from other discours? If we limit our remarks to the author of a book or a text, we can isolate four different characteristics. First of all, discours are objects of appropriation. The form of ownership from which they spring is of a rather particular type, one that has been codified for many years. We should note that, historically, this type of ownership has always been subquent to what one might call penal appropriation. Texts, books, and discours really began to have authors (other than mythical, sacralized and sacralizing figures) to the extent that authors became subject to punishment, that is, to the extent that discours could be transgressive. In our culture (and doubtless in many others), discour was not originally a product, a thing, a kind of goods; it was esntially an act - an act placed in the bipolar field of the sacred and the profane, the licit and the illicit, the religious and the blasphemous. Historically, it was a gesture fraught with risks before becoming goods caught up in a circuit of ownership. Once a system of ownership for texts came into being, once strict rules concerning author's rights, author-publisher relations, rights of reproduction, and related matters were enacted - at the end of the eighteenth and the beginning of the nineteenth century - the possibility of transgression attached to the act of writing took on, more and more, the form of an imperative peculiar to literature. It is as if the author, beginning with the moment at which he was placed in the system of property that characterizes our society, compensated for the status that he thus acquired by rediscovering the old bipolar field of discour, systematically practicing transgression and thereby restoring danger to a writing that was now guaranteed the benefits of ownership. The author function does not affect all discours in a universal and constant way, however. In our civilization, it has not always been the same types of texts that have required attribution to an author. There was a time when the texts we today call "literary" (narratives, stories, epics, tragedies, comedies) were accepted, put into circulation, and valorized without any question about the identity of their author, their anonymity caud no difficulties since their ancientness, whether real or imagined, was regarded as a sufficient guarantee of their status. On the other hand, tho texts we now would call scientific - tho dealing with cosmology and the heavens, medicine and illness, natural sciences and geography - were accepted in the Middle Ages, and accepted as "true," only when marked with the name of their author. "Hippocrates said," "Pliny recounts," were not really formulas of an argument bad on authority; they were the markers inrted in discours that were suppod to be received as statements of demonstrated truth. A switch takes place in the venteenth or eighteenth century. Scientific discours began to be received for themlves, in the anonymity of an established or always redemonstrable truth; their membership in a systematic enmble, and not the reference to the individual who produced them, stood as their guarantee. The author function faded away, and the inventor's name rved only to christen a theorem, proposition, particular effect, property, body, group of elements, or pathological syndrome. By the same token, literary discours came to be accepted only when endowed with the author function. We now ask of each poetic or fictional text: From where does it come, who wrote it, when, under what circumstances, or beginning with what design? The meaning ascribed to it and the status or value accorded it depend on the manner in which we answer the questions. And if a text should be discovered in a state of anonymity – whether as a conquence of an accident or the author's explicit wish – the game becomes one of rediscovering the author. Since literary anonymity is not tolerable, we can accept it only in the gui of an enigma. As a result, the author function today plays an important role in our view of literary works. (The are obviously generalizations that would have to be refined insofar as recent critical practice is concerned. Criticism began some time ago to treat works according to their genre and type, following the recurrent elements that are enfigured in them, as proper variations around an invariant that is no longer the individual creator. Even so, if in mathematics reference to the author is barely anything any longer but a manner of naming theorems or ts of propositions, in biology and medicine the indication of the author and the date of his work playa rather different role. It is not simply a manner of indicating the source, but of providing a certain index of "reality" in relation to the techniques and objects of experience made u of in a particular period and in such-and-such a laboratory.) The third characteristic of this author function is that it does not develop spontaneously as the attribution of a discour to an individual. It is, rather, the result of a complex operation that constructs a certain being of reason that we call "author." Critics doubtless try to give this being of reason a realistic status, by discerning, in the individual, a "deep" motive, a "creative" power, or a "design," the milieu in which writing originates. Nevertheless, the aspects of an individual which we designate as making him an author are only a projection, in more or less psychologizing terms, of the operations we force texts to undergo, the connections we make, the traits we establish as pertinent, the continuities we recognize, or the exclusions we practice. All the operations vary according to periods and types of discour. We do not-construct a "philosophical author" as we do a "poet," just as in the eighteenth century one did not construct a novelist as we do today. StilI, we can find through the ages certain constants in the rules of author construction. It ems, for example that the manner in which literary criticism once defined the author – or, rather, constructed the figure of the author beginning with existing texts and discours – is directly derived from the manner in which Christian tradition authenticated (or rejected) the texts at its disposal. In order to "rediscover" an author in a work, modern criticism us methods similar to tho that Christian exegesis employed when trying to prove the value of a text by its author's saintliness. In De Viris Mustribus, Saint Jerome explains that homonymy is not sufficient to identify legitimately authors of more than one work: different individuals could have had the same name, or one man could have, illegitimately, borrowed another's patronymic. The name as an individual trademark is not enough when one works within a textual tradition. How, then, can one attribute veral discours to one and the same author? How can one u the author function to determine if one is dealing with one or veral individuals? Saint Jerome propos four criteria: (i) if among veral books attributed to an author one is inferior to the others, it must be withdrawn from the list of the author's works (the author is therefore defined as a constant level of value); (2) the same should be done if certain texts contradict the doctrine expounded in the author's other works (the author is thus defined as a field of conceptual or theoretical coherence); (3) one must also exclude works that are written in a different style, containing words and expressions not ordinarily found in the writer's production (the author is here conceived as a stylistic unity); (4) finally, passages quoting statements made or mentioning events that occurred after the author's death must be regarded as interpolated texts (the author is here en as a historical figure at the crossroads of a certain number of events). Modern literary criticism, even when – as is now customary – it is not concerned with questions of authentication, still defines the author in much the same way: the author provides the basis for explaining not only the prence of certain events in a work, but also their transformations, distortions, and diver modifications (through his biography, the determination of his individual perspective, the analysis of his social position, and the revelation of his basic design). The author is also the principle of a certain unity of writing - all differences having to be resolved, at least in part, by the principles of evolution, maturation, or influence. The author also rves to neutralize the contradictions that may emerge in a ries of texts: there must be - at a certain level of his thought or desire, of his consciousness or unconscious - a point where contradictions are resolved, where incompatible elements are at last tied together or organized around a fundamental or originating contradiction. Finally, the author is a particular source of expression that, in more or less completed forms, is manifested equally well, and with similar validity, in works, sketches, letters, fragments, and so on. Clearly, Saint Jerome's four criteria of authenticity (criteria that em totally insufficient for today's exegetes) do define the four modalities according to which modern criticism brings the author function into play. But the author function is not a pure and simple reconstruction made condhand from a text given as inert material. The text always contains a certain number of signs referring to the author. The signs, well known to grammarians, are personal pronouns, adverbs of time and place, and verb conjugation. Such elements do not play the same role in discours provided with the author function as in tho lacking it. In the latter, such "shifters" refer to the real speaker and to the spatio-temporal coordinates of his discour (although certain modifications can occur, as in the operation of relating discours in the first person). In the former, however, their role is more complex and variable. Everyone knows that, in a novel offered as a narrator's account, neither the first-person pronoun nor the prent indicative refers exactly to the writer or to the moment in which he writes but, rather, to an alter ego who distance from the author varies, often changing in the cour of the work. It would be just as wrong to equate the author with the real writer as to equate him with the fictitious speaker; the author function is carried out and operates in the scission itlf, in this division and this distance. One might object that this is a characteristic peculiar to novelistic or poetic discour, a game in which only "quasi discours" participate. In fact, however, all discours endowed with the author function posss this plurality of lf. The lf that speaks in the preface to a treati on mathematics - and that indicates the circumstances of the treati's composition identical neither in its position nor in its functioning to lf speaks in the cour of a demonstration, and that appears the form of "I conclude" or "I suppo." In the first ca, the "I" refers to an individual without an equivalent who, in a determined place and time, completed a certain task; in the cond, the "I" indicates an instance and a level of demonstration which any individual could perform provided that he accepted the same system of symbols, play of axioms and t of previous demonstrations. We could also, in the same treati locate a third lf; one that speaks to tell the work's meaning, the obstacles encountered, the results obtained, and the remaining problems; this lf is situated in the field of already existing or yet-to-appear mathematical discours. The author function is not assumed by the first of the lves at the expen of the other two, which would then be nothing more than a fictitious splitting in two of the first one. On the contrary, in the discours the author function operates so as to effect the dispersion of the three simultaneous lves. No doubt, analysis could discover still more characteristic traits of the author function. I will limit mylf to the four, however, becau they em both the most visible and the most important. They can be summarized as follows:(1) the author function is linked to the juridical and institutional system that encompass, determines, and articulates the univer of discours; (2) it does not affect all discours in the same way at all times and in all types of civilization; (3) it is not defined by the spontaneous attribution of a discour to its producer but, rather, by a ries of specific and complex operations; (4) it does not refer purely and simply to a real individual, since it can give ri simultaneously to veral lves, to veral subjects - positions that can be occupied by different class of individuals. 裙子的英语Up to this point I have unjustifiably limited my subject. Certainly the author function in painting, music, and other arts should have been discusd; but even supposing that we remain within the world of discour, as I want to do, I em to have given the term "author" much too narrow a meaning. I have discusd the author only in the limited n of a person to whom the production of a text, a book, or a work can be legitimately attributed. It is easy to e that in the sphere of discour one can be the author of much more than a book - one can be the author of a theory, tradition, or discipline in which other books and authors will in their turn find a place. The authors are in a position that I will call "trans-discursive." This is a recurring phenomenon – certainly as old as our civilization. Homer, Aristotle, and the Church Fathers, as well as the first mathematicians and the originators of the Hippocratic tradition, all played this role. Furthermore, in the cour of the nineteenth century, there appeared in Europe another, more uncommon, kind of author, whom one should confu with neither the "great" literary authors, nor the authors of religious texts, nor the founders of science. In a somewhat arbitrary way we shall call tho who belong in this last group "founders of discursivity." They are unique in that they are not just the authors of their own works. They have produced something el: the possibilities and the rules for the formation of other texts. In this n they are very different, for example, from a novelist, who is, in fact, nothing more than the author of his own text. Freud is not just the author of The Interpretation of Dreams or Jokes and Their Relation to the Unconscious; Marx is not just the author of the Communist Manifesto or peeloffDas Kapitallec: they both have established an endless possibility of discour. Obviously, it is easy to object. One might say that it is not true that the author of a novel is only the author of his own text; in a n, he also, provided that he acquires some "importance," governs and commands more than that. To take a very simple example, one could say that Ann Radcliffe not only wrote The Castles of Athlin and Dunbayne and veral other novels but also made possible the appearance of the Gothic horror novel at the beginning of the nineteenth century; in that respect, her author function exceeds her own work. But I think there is an answer to this objection. The founders of discursivity (I u Marx and Freud as examples, becau I believe them to be both the first and the most important cas) make possible something altogether different from what a novelist makes possible. Ann Radcliffe's texts opened the way for a certain number of remblances and analogies which have their model or principle in her work. The latter contains characteristic signs, figures, relationships, and structures that could be reud by others. In other words, to say that Ann Radcliffe founded the Gothic horror novel means that in the nineteenth-century Gothic novel one will find, as in Ann Radcliffe's works, the theme of the heroine caught in the trap of her own innocence, the hidden castle, the character of the black, curd hero devoted to making the world expiate the evil done to him, and all the rest of it. On the other hand, when I speak of Marx or Freud as founders of discursivity, I mean that they made possible not only a certain number of analogies but also (and equally important) a certain number of differences. They have created a possibility for something other than their discour, yet something belonging to what they founded. To say that Freud founded psychoanalysis does not (simply) mean that we find the concept of the libido or the technique of dream analysis in the works of Karl Abraham, or Melanie Klein; it means that Freud made possible a certain number of divergences – with respect to his own texts, concepts and hypothes – that all ari from the psychoanalytic discour itlf. This would em to prent a new difficulty, however, or at least a new problem: is the above not true, after all, of any founder of a science, or of any author who has introduced some transformation into a science that might be called fecund? After all, Galileo made possible not only tho discours which repeated the laws he had formulated, but also statements very different from what he himlf had said. If Georges Cuvier is the founder of biology, or Ferdinand de Saussure the founder of linguistics, it is not becau they were imitated, nor becau people have since taken up again the concept of organism or sign; it is becau Cuvier made possible, to a certain extent, a theory of evolution diametrically oppod to his own fixism; it is becau Saussure made possible a generative grammar radically different from his structural analys. Superficially, then, the initiation of discursive practices appears similar to the founding of any scientific endeavor. Still, there is a difference, and a notable one. In the ca of a science, the act that founds it is on an equal footing with its future transformations; this act becomes in some respects part of the t of modifications that I makes possible. Of cour, this belonging can take veral forms. In the future development of a science, the founding act may appear as little more than a particular instance of a more general phenomenon that unveils itlf in the process. It can also turn out to be marred by intuition and empirical bias; one must then reformulate it, making it the object of a certain number of supplementary theoretical operations that establish it more rigorously, and so on. Finally, it can em to be a hasty generalization that must be retraced. In other words, the founding act of a science can always be reintroduced within the machinery of tho transformations which derive from it. In contrast, the initiation of a discursive practice is heterogeneous to its subquent transformations. To expand a type of discursivity such as psychoanalysis as founded by Freud, is not to give it a form generality it would not have permitted at the outt but, rather, open it up to a certain number of possible applications. To limit psy choanalysis as a type of discursivity is, in reality, to try to isolate in the founding act an eventually restricted number of propositions or statements to which, alone, one grants a founding value, and in relation to which certain concepts or theories accepted by Freud might be considered as derived, condary, and accessory. In addition, one does not declare certain propositions in the work of the founders to be fal: instead, when trying to ize the act of founding, one ts aside tho statements that are not pertinent, either becau they are deemed inesntial, or becau they are considered "prehistoric" and derived from another type of discursivity. In other words, unlike the founding of a science, the initiation of a discursive practice does not participate in its later transformations. As a result, one defines a proposition's theoretical validity in relation to the work of the founders - while, in the ca of Galileo and Newton, it is in relation to what physics or cosmology is in its intrinsic structure and normativity that one affirms the validity of any proposition tho men may have put forth. To phra it very schematically: the work of initiators of discursivity is not situated in the space that science defines; rather, it is the science or the discursivity which refers back to their work as primary coordinates. In this way we can understand the inevitable necessity, within the fields of discursivity, for a "return to the origin." This return which is part of the discursive field itlf, never stops modifying it. The return is not a historical supplement that would be added to the discursivity, or merely an ornament; on the contrary, it constitutes a effective and necessary task of transforming the discursive practice itlf. Reexamination of Galileo's text may well change our understanding of the history of mechanics, but it will never be able to change mechanics itlf. On the other hand, reexamining Freud's texts modifies psychoanalysis itlf, just as a reexamination of Marx's would modify Marxism. What I have just outlined regarding the "discursive instaurations" is, of cour, very schematic; this is true, in particular, of the opposition I have tried to draw between discursive initiation and scientific founding. It is not always easy to distinguish between the two; moreover, nothing proves that they are two mutually exclusive procedures. I have attempted the distinction for only one reason: to show that the author function, which is complex enough when one tries to situate it at the level of a book or a ries of texts that carry a given signature, involves still more determining factors when one tries to analyze it in larger units; such as groups of works or entire disciplines. § To conclude, I would like to review the reasons why I attach a certain importance to what l have said. On the one hand, an analysis in the direction that I have outlined might provide for an approach to a typology of discour. It ems to me, at least at first glance, that such a typology cannot be constructed solely from the grammatical features, formal structures, and objects of discour: more likely, there exist properties or relationships peculiar to discour (not reducible to the rules of grammar and logic), and one must u the to distinguish the major categories of discour. The relationship (or non-relationship) with an author, and the different forms this relationship takes, constitute – in a quite visible manner – one of the discursive properties. On the other hand, I believe that one could find here an introduction to the historical analysis of discour. Perhaps it is time to study discours not only in terms of their expressive value or formal transformations but according to their modes of existence. The modes of circulation, valorization, attribution, and appropriation of discours vary with each culture and are modified within each. The manner in which they are articulated according to social relationships can be more readily understood, I believe, in the activity of the author function and in its modifications than in the themes or concepts that discours t in motion. It would em that one could also, beginning with analys of this type, reexamine the privileges of the subject. I realize that in undertaking the internal and architectonic analysis of a work (be it a literary text, philosophical system, or scientific work), in tting aside biographical and psychological references, one has already called back into question the absolute character and founding role of the subject. Still, perhaps one must return to this question, not in order to reestablish the theme of an originating subject but to grasp the subject's points of inrtion, modes of functioning, and system of dependencies. Doing so means overturning the traditional problem, no longer raising the questions: How can a free subject penetrate the density of things and give it meaning? How can it activate the rules of a language from within and thus give ri to the designs that are properly its own? Instead, the questions will be raid: How, under what conditions, and in what forms can something like a subject appear in the order of discour? What place can it occupy in each type of discour, what functions can it assume, and by obeying what rules? In short, it is a matter of depriving the subject (or its substitute) of its role as originator, and of analyzing the subject as a variable and complex function of discour. Second, there are reasons dealing with the "ideological" status of the author. The question then becomes: How can one reduce the great peril, the great danger with which fiction threatens our world? The answer is: One can reduce it with the author. The author allows a limitation of the cancerous and dangerous proliferation of significations within a world where one is thrifty not only with one's resources and riches but also with one's discours and their significations. The author is the principle of thrift in the proliferation of meaning. As a result, we must entirely rever the traditional idea of the author. We are accustomed, as we have en earlier, to saying that the author is the genial creator of a work in which he deposits, with infinite wealth and generosity, an inexhaustible world of significations. We are ud to thinking that the author is so different from all other men, and so transcendent with regard to all languages that, as soon as he speaks, meaning begins to proliferate, to proliferate indefinitely. The truth is quite the contrary: the author is not an indefinite source of significations that fill a work; the author does not precede the works; he is a certain functional principle by which, in our culture, one limits, excludes, and choos; in short, by which one impedes the free circulation, the free manipulation, the free composition, decomposition, and recomposition of fiction. In fact, if we are accustomed to prenting the author as a genius, as a perpetual surging of invention, it is becau, in reality, we make him function in exactly the opposite fashion. One can say that the author is an ideological product, since we reprent him as the opposite of his historically real function. When a historically given function is reprented in a figure that inrts it, one has an ideological production. The author is therefore the ideological figure by which one marks the manner in which we fear the proliferation of meaning. In saying this, I em to call for a form of culture in which fiction would not be limited by the figure of the author. It would be pure romanticism, however, to imagine a culture in which the fictive would operate in an absolutely free state, in which fiction would be put at the disposal of everyone and would develop without passing through something like a necessary or constraining figure. Although, since the eighteenth century, the author has played the role of the regulator of the fictive; a role quite characteristic of our era of industrial and bourgeois society, of individualism and private property, still, given the historical modifications that are taking place, it does not em necessary that the author function remain constant in form, complexity, and even in existence. I think that, as our society changes, at the very moment when it is in the process of changing, the author function will disappear, and in such a manner that fiction and its polymous texts will once again function according to another mode, but still with a system of constraint – one that will no longer be the author but will have to be determined or, perhaps, experienced [expérimenter]. All discours, whatever their status, form, value, and whatever the treatment to which they will be subjected, would then develop in the anonymity of a murmur. We would no longer hear the questions that have been rehashed for so long: Who really spoke? Is it really he and not someone el? With what authenticity or originality? And what part of his deepest ll did he express in his discour? Instead, there would be other questions, like the: What are the modes of existence of this discour? Where has it been ud, how can it circulate, and who can appropriate it for himlf? What are the places in it where there is room for possible subjects? Who can assume the various subject functions? And behind all the questions, we would hear hardly anything but the stirring of an indifference: What difference does it make who is speaking? § cardioNOTES i John Searle, Essay in the philosophy of language (Cambridge, Eng.: Cambridge University Press, 1969) pp. 162-74 |
*This essay is the text of a lecture prented to the Societé Francais de philosophie on 22 February 1969 (Foucault gave a modified form of the lecture in the United States in 1970). This translation by Josué V. Harari has been slightly modified. |
本文发布于:2023-07-13 06:13:55,感谢您对本站的认可!
本文链接:https://www.wtabcd.cn/fanwen/fan/78/1093851.html
版权声明:本站内容均来自互联网,仅供演示用,请勿用于商业和其他非法用途。如果侵犯了您的权益请与我们联系,我们将在24小时内删除。
留言与评论(共有 0 条评论) |